The translation of anaphoric relations



next up previous
Next: Conclusion Up: AN APPROACH TO SENTENCE-LEVEL Previous: Implementation

The translation of anaphoric relations

In this section, we intend to give an impression of the usefulness of coindex relations in translation and the translation of the relations themselves. In linguistics, a monolingual account of coindexation is quite an achievement. In machine translation, the most important part of research deals with the translation of the relations that were established monolingually.

The I-object to be translated consists of an I-structure annotated with anaphoric relations. An I-object is the result of the application of certain anaphoric relations (denoted by the annotations) to a particular I-structure. The compositional translation of an I-object is the result of the application of the translated annotations to the translated I-structure. We hold the view that anaphoric relations are universal in MiMo. The translation of a relation between the I-structures I and J is that same relation between the translations of I and J. This is summarized in (29).

(29) the translation of an I-object:
The translation of an I-object I1 is the result of the application of the translations of the annotations of I1 to the translation of I1's I-structure. The translation of an annotation R(I,J) is R(t(I),t(J)).

The final set of anaphoric relations of the target object should be equivalent to the set that existed at the source level. The following example illustrates principle (30) :

(30) Por que [ dice Juan [ que [ los dos creian [ que [ Pedro habia pensado [ que [ el grupo habia aplazado la reunion
Why say John that the two thought that Peter believed that the group postponed the meeting

Inversion being obligatory in all clauses except the lowest, 'por que' can only bind the modifier position in either the first or the second clause. Each relation further down is excluded as more clauses would have to show inversion then. When we ignore the bindings established at the Spanish I-level, translation into English will produce a lot of possible translations since 'that' may or may not be inserted in every complementizer position in English. However, the impact of this complementizer on possible anaphoric relations is not totally irrelevant. According to WAHL (1987), the complementizer blocks binding of 'why' to an empty position deeper down, cf. (31) and (32).

(31) why(i)/(j) do you think _(i) the boat sank _(j)
(32) why(i) do you think _(i) that the boat sank _

When we preserve the bindings from Spanish and we claim that in English 'that' may never be inserted when its modifier position is bound to an antecedent, we can deterministically arrive at the right translation :

(33) Por que [ dice Juan [ que [ los dos creian [ que [ Pedro habia pensado [ que [ el grupo habia aplazado la reunion
(34) Why [ did John say [ [ the two thought [ that [ Peter believed [ (that) the group had postponed the meeting

Both are ambiguous since both can question the reason for John's 'saying it' and 'the two believing it'. Other interpretations are excluded in both Spanish and English.

Definition (29) also causes some problems. Take the following example from Italian (cf. Chomsky 1981) :

(35) l'uomo [che mi domando [chi abbia visto]]
the man(i) of whom I wonder who(j) e(i) saw e(j)

One might wonder what the English translation would have to be in the first place. In MiMo, the incorrect literal translation will not be found because the necessary anaphoric relations cannot be established. In cases like these, separate translation rules are needed to arrive at a translation of (35). It is possible to refer explicitly to anaphoric relations as long as they are restricted in depth. This is necessary in case an expression without anaphoric relations translates into one which requires a linking between an antecedent and an anaphor. An example is (36).

(36) Jan zwemt graag John(i) likes _(i) to swim

Unboundedly deep embedded relations are however not accessible by translation rules in the transfer component. Another problem we face deals with the interaction of anaphora and other standard 'non-compositional' phenomena, such as the example of Dutch 'graag' translating as 'to like' in English (see section 1). These examples, as well as anaphora, can be handled compositionally, as we have shown. The interaction however poses some problems, see (37).

(37) Hoe graag zwom Jan How much did John like to swim

Since 'graag' is displaced, translation of 'graag' as the exceptional part of the embedded sentence is not possible, given that the movement is not undonepng . These cases are even noncompositional from MiMo's tolerant view on compositionality.


next up previous
Next: Conclusion Up: AN APPROACH TO SENTENCE-LEVEL Previous: Implementation



Gertjan van Noord
Fri Nov 25 13:16:14 MET 1994